Moral Objectivism and Moral Utilitarianism

Research Article
Open access

Moral Objectivism and Moral Utilitarianism

Xuanze Shi 1*
  • 1 Wake Forest University, Winston-Salem, North Carolina, United State, 27109    
  • *corresponding author shix20@wfu.edu
CHR Vol.4
ISSN (Print): 2753-7072
ISSN (Online): 2753-7064
ISBN (Print): 978-1-915371-31-7
ISBN (Online): 978-1-915371-32-4

Abstract

Morality is the standard that can guide and restrict the behaviors of people, and it has played an important role during the past centuries. Two questions remain unsolved by philosophers. The first problem is the existence of objective morality and if there is such an objective morality, the other problem is the content of morality. It is important to discuss these problems because they can play a significant role in helping people understand and develop the right morality. For these two problems, the author aims to argue that moral objectivism and moral utilitarianism are true. For objectivism, the author will argue the problem of lacking such an objective morality. For utilitarianism, the author will explain its meaning, argue against several objections, and present its application in his personal life. This paper argues that moral objectivism and utilitarianism are true.

Keywords:

moral utilitarianism, moral objectivism, moral subjectivism, morality, moral egoism

Shi,X. (2023). Moral Objectivism and Moral Utilitarianism. Communications in Humanities Research,4,204-208.
Export citation

References

[1]. Beebe, Qiaoan, R., Wysocki, T., & Endara, M. A. (2015). Moral Objectivism in Cross-Cultural Perspective. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 15(3-4), 386–401. https://doi.org/10.1163/15685373-12342157

[2]. Gunnar Björnsson. (2012). Do “Objectivist” Features of Moral Discourse and Thinking Support Moral Objectivism? The Journal of Ethics, 16(4), 367–393. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9131-9

[3]. Zijlstra. (2019). Folk moral objectivism and its measurement. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 84, 103807. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2019.04.005

[4]. Trémolière, & Gosling, C. J. (2021). Association of natural sleep with moral utilitarianism: No evidence from 6 preregistered studies. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 28(5), 1726–1734. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-021-01945-6

[5]. Sarkissian, & Phelan, M. (2019). Moral objectivism and a punishing God. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 80, 1–7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2018.08.012

[6]. Gustafsson. (2021). Utilitarianism without Moral Aggregation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 51(4), 256–269. https://doi.org/10.1017/can.2021.20

[7]. Bègue, & Laine, P.-J. (2017). Moral Utilitarianism and Attitudes Toward Animals. Ethics & Behavior, 27(3), 173–178. https://doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2016.1162720

[8]. Hartner. (2020). Moral Context, Moral Complicity, And Ethical Theory. Sats (Aarhus), 21(2), 179–198. https://doi.org/10.1515/sats-2020-2011

[9]. Kaplow, & Shavell, S. (2007). Moral Rules, the Moral Sentiments, and Behavior: Toward a Theory of an Optimal Moral System. The Journal of Political Economy, 115(3), 494–514. https://doi.org/10.1086/519927

[10]. CRISP. (2010). VIRTUE ETHICS AND VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY. Metaphilosophy, 41(1-2), 22–40. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9973.2009.01621.x


Cite this article

Shi,X. (2023). Moral Objectivism and Moral Utilitarianism. Communications in Humanities Research,4,204-208.

Data availability

The datasets used and/or analyzed during the current study will be available from the authors upon reasonable request.

Disclaimer/Publisher's Note

The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of EWA Publishing and/or the editor(s). EWA Publishing and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

About volume

Volume title: Proceedings of the International Conference on Interdisciplinary Humanities and Communication Studies (ICIHCS 2022), Part 2

ISBN:978-1-915371-31-7(Print) / 978-1-915371-32-4(Online)
Editor:Faraz Ali Bughio, David T. Mitchell
Conference website: https://www.icihcs.org/
Conference date: 18 December 2022
Series: Communications in Humanities Research
Volume number: Vol.4
ISSN:2753-7064(Print) / 2753-7072(Online)

© 2024 by the author(s). Licensee EWA Publishing, Oxford, UK. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license. Authors who publish this series agree to the following terms:
1. Authors retain copyright and grant the series right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution License that allows others to share the work with an acknowledgment of the work's authorship and initial publication in this series.
2. Authors are able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the non-exclusive distribution of the series's published version of the work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), with an acknowledgment of its initial publication in this series.
3. Authors are permitted and encouraged to post their work online (e.g., in institutional repositories or on their website) prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (See Open access policy for details).

References

[1]. Beebe, Qiaoan, R., Wysocki, T., & Endara, M. A. (2015). Moral Objectivism in Cross-Cultural Perspective. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 15(3-4), 386–401. https://doi.org/10.1163/15685373-12342157

[2]. Gunnar Björnsson. (2012). Do “Objectivist” Features of Moral Discourse and Thinking Support Moral Objectivism? The Journal of Ethics, 16(4), 367–393. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9131-9

[3]. Zijlstra. (2019). Folk moral objectivism and its measurement. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 84, 103807. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2019.04.005

[4]. Trémolière, & Gosling, C. J. (2021). Association of natural sleep with moral utilitarianism: No evidence from 6 preregistered studies. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 28(5), 1726–1734. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-021-01945-6

[5]. Sarkissian, & Phelan, M. (2019). Moral objectivism and a punishing God. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 80, 1–7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2018.08.012

[6]. Gustafsson. (2021). Utilitarianism without Moral Aggregation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 51(4), 256–269. https://doi.org/10.1017/can.2021.20

[7]. Bègue, & Laine, P.-J. (2017). Moral Utilitarianism and Attitudes Toward Animals. Ethics & Behavior, 27(3), 173–178. https://doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2016.1162720

[8]. Hartner. (2020). Moral Context, Moral Complicity, And Ethical Theory. Sats (Aarhus), 21(2), 179–198. https://doi.org/10.1515/sats-2020-2011

[9]. Kaplow, & Shavell, S. (2007). Moral Rules, the Moral Sentiments, and Behavior: Toward a Theory of an Optimal Moral System. The Journal of Political Economy, 115(3), 494–514. https://doi.org/10.1086/519927

[10]. CRISP. (2010). VIRTUE ETHICS AND VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY. Metaphilosophy, 41(1-2), 22–40. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9973.2009.01621.x